CAIN AND ABEL AS CHARACTER TRAITS:

A STUDY IN THE ALLEGORICAL TYPOLOGY
OF PHILO OF ALEXANDRIA[1]

 

Hindy Najman

 

 

The writings of Philo of Alexandria contain three extensive treatments of the Cain and Abel narrative: On the Sacrifices of Abel and Cain, The Worse Attacks the Better, and On the Posterity and Exile of Cain. This paper will argue that PhiloÕs interpretation of Cain and Abel is typological, and that the types in question are both cosmological and psycho­logical. The types of Cain and Abel are presented as two aspects of the human soul, representing the human capacity for good and the human capacity for evil. Consequently, reflection on these two types can be a source of moral teaching.

My argument may sound controversial. For Philo is sometimes said not to practice typological interpretation at all, but rather alle­gorical interpretation, and the two kinds of interpretation are some­times thought to be mutually exclusive. Before turning to the details of PhiloÕs interpretation of the Cain and Abel narratives, then, I will first discuss the nature of typology and its relationship to allegory. As I will argue, the idea that they are mutually exclusive arises from particular theological presuppositions and has unfortunate conse­quences for the study of the history of ancient biblical interpreta­tion. I will also question the claim that Philo does not engage in typological interpretation by considering PhiloÕs interpretations and terminology. PhiloÕs interpretation of the story of EveÕs children, I will argue, is at once both typological and allegorical, and it provides an important illustration of what is theologically and historiograph­ically at stake.

 

I

 

Allegory and typology have often been contrasted as two fundamen­tally different ways of interpreting Scripture. While allegorical inter­pretation has been said to focus on the cosmic and the spiritual, typological interpretation has been characterized as more historical and literal.[2] However, although it is true that allegorical interpreta­tion tends to be cosmological and that typological interpretations tend to be oriented towards history, the distinction between the two is less clearcut than one might think. Since the reformation, scholars have denigrated allegorical interpretation (e.g., in the writings of Philo of Alexandria and of Origen) because it appeared far removed from the literal sense of Scripture. Instead, typological interpretation (e.g., in the writings of Paul) was celebrated.[3] The focus on the literal sense of Scriptureand, since the enlightenment, on historical study of the Bibleproduced antiallegorical polemics that still find their way into current scholarship.

Philo himself uses the term ÒtuposÓ throughout his writings, so one would think that there is good reason to call his interpretations typo­logical.[4] Still many scholars deny that Philo engages in typological exegesis at all. For example, Goppelt writes:

 

PhiloÕs exposition of patriarchal history contains no typological inter­pretation at all. Whenever the historicity of the patriarchs has not been completely destroyed by allegory, they are presented as ethical Òtypes,Ó or ideals, and do not fit our definition according to which a type must point to something greater in the future.[5]

 

In this passage, typological interpretation is restricted to a particu­lar kind of historical typology that can be found in the New Testament. Central use of the term ÒtuposÓ in an interpretation is insufficient, according to Goppelt, for classification of that interpretation as typo­logical. It is also required that the interpretation operate within the framework of salvation history. It is in this sense of historicity[6] that typology is said to be historical, whereas allegorical exegesis is said to be symbolic, spiritual and interested only in the cosmic and the eternal, not in the narrative of Scripture.

It seems an odd policy to apply the term Òtypological interpreta­tionÓ only to interpretations with particular theological presupposi­tions. Indeed, others use such presuppositions to distinguish different species of typology instead. Thus, for example, Woolcombe writes:

 

There is no theological similarity whatever between the typology of Philo and that of St Paul. The only point of contact between the two writ­ers is their common use of the typological vocabulary. But whereas in St Paul the vocabulary is harnessed to the exposition of GodÕs redemp­tive work in history, in Philo it is harnessed to allegorism. It is in fact hardly possible to separate typology from allegorism in Philo, and if the word typology must be used of certain aspects of Philonic exege­sis, it should always be qualified by the adjective symbolic, in con­tradistinction to the historical typology of the New Testament.[7]

 

However, the extreme language in this passageÒno theological sim­ilarity whateverÓ, nothing more than a lexical Òpoint of contactÓ­—suggests that it has the same underlying motivation as the outright denial that Philo practices typological interpretation: to enforce the sense of a radical distinction between Jewish and Christian modes of exegesis. From a scholarly viewpoint, such motivations should be suspect. For they are all but bound to lead to the effacement of the profound exegetical and theological continuities between ancient Judaism and early Christianity.[8]

Nevertheless, Woolcombe is night to say that, it is Òhardly possi­ble to separate typology from allegorism in PhiloÓ. PhiloÕs typological interpretation should be seen as a species of allegorical interpreta­tion. Indeed, as the term ÒallegorismÓ suggests, Philo is interested in explaining the cosmic significance of biblical texts. This interest should not, however, be misrepresented as incompatible with respect for the literal meaning of the biblical text, whether narrative or legal. As Goppelt writes:

 

He [Philo] retells and explains biblical history and the very details of patriarchal and Mosaic history. Above all, he insists that the literal sense of the Law must be fulfilled, quite apart from its deepermean­ing (Migr. Abr. 8993; Exsecr. 154).[9]

 

For Philo, the narrative of Israel is the story of a community that strives for perfection by observing Mosaic Law. But observance of Mosaic Law requires not only attention to the laws in the Torah but also use of biblical narratives within a moral pedagogy rooted within a deep account of the complexity of the human soul. Indeed, as I will argue, PhiloÕs typological analysis of the Cain and Abel nar­ratives should be understood as an exercise not only in cosmology but also in moral psychology and paideia.[10]

 

II

 

It is not difficult to show that the term tupos plays an important role in PhiloÕs exegesis. For example, in De Opificio Mundi 18, tupoi are implemented by the creator from the archetype or paradigm of the overall plan for the cosmos:

 

Thus after having received in his own soul, as it were in wax, the figures of these objects severally, he carries about the image of a city which is the creation of his mind. Then by his innate power of mem­ory, he recalls the images of the various parts of this city, and imprints their types yet more distinctly in it: and like a good craftsman he begins to build the city of stones and timber, keeping his eye upon his pattern and making the visible and tangible objects correspond in each case to the incorporeal ideas.

 

In another example from De Decalogo 1011, Philo describes trans­gressions upon the soul as tupoi and suggests that reeducating the soul is a precondition for receiving the law:

 

He who is about to receive the holy laws must first cleanse his soul and purge away the deepset stains which it has contracted through contact with the motley promiscuous horde of men in cities. And to this he cannot attain except by dwelling apart, nor that at once but only long afterwards, and not till the marks which his old transgres­sions have imprinted on him gradually grown faint, melted away and disappeared.

 

As in the above two examples, PhiloÕs writings are replete with ref­erences to tupos. In fact, ÒtuposÓ is a prominent member of a chain of words that appear in PhiloÕs interpretations. Other members of the chain include ÒeikonÓ (image or copy), ÒcharacterÓ (stamp, stan­dard, or figure of letters, but also character type) and ÒPhantasiaÓ (impression or appearance). Perhaps it is helpful to think of tupos as character[11] or, more specifically, character trait. The English or Greek word Òcharacte~Õ like ÒtypeÓ has a meaning with two dimensions.

1) A tupos or character is a legible imprint. It is a mark left by something else, which the mark now resembles as an image resem­bles an original. I will call this the copying dimension of the mean­ing of tupos. A tupos is a copy or eikon of some original, which Philo calls an archetupos or paradigma. For example, according to Philo the archetype of evil is Cain, so every selflover shares in CainÕs sin and in the murder of Abel:

 

Wherefore let every lover of self, surnamed ÒCain,Ó be taught that he has slain that which shares AbelÕs name, the specimen, the part, the impression stamped to resemble him, not the original, not the class, not the pattern, though he fancies that these, which are imperishable, have perished together with the living beings. Let some one say, taunt­ing and ridiculing him: What have you done, poor wretch? Does not the Godloving creed, which you imagine you have annihilated, live with God? You have proved to be your own murderer, having slain by guile that which alone had the power to enable you to live a guilt­less life. (Det. 78)

 

Thus according to Philo, types are less perfect than the originals, yet they imitate the originals and resemble them as copies of those originals.

2) A tupos or character trait is a disposition to act in a particular way, a virtue or a vice. It is a disposition that a human being may acquire through habit or education. I will call this the psychological dimension of the meaning of tupos. Here it is important to note that, as with a piece of wax, i character trait imprinted upon a human soul may be effaced, and the soul may be restamped with a different, even opposite character trait. Hence the fragility of virtue. For there is no guarantee that a soul will retain the good character with which it has been imprinted. As Philo writes:

 

The mind, like wax, receives the impress and retains it vividly, until forgetfulness, the opponent of memory levels out the imprint, and makes it indistinct, or entirely effaces it. (Deus 44)

 

But the wax analogy also implies the possibility of repentance. For a bad character trait, just like a good one, may be replaced. Here Philo is perhaps reworking PlatoÕs discussion of the waxen imprints upon the soul in Theaetetus 191c ff. However, Plato is concerned with the apprehension and retention of knowledge, while Philo focuses on the moral formation of the soul through action.

Philo seems to believe, not only that all human beings have the capacity for virtuous behavior, but also that everyone is actually born in a state of goodness. It is then left to each individual to reinforce this innate goodness through good action, or else it will be com­promised through transgression. Notably, not every place is con­ducive to virtuous behavior. Most famously, Philo insists that the city is a place of corruption. That is why Israel must leave Egypt and receive the law in the desert (Decal. 11).

It is helpful to compare IsraelÕs need to leave the city with the philosopherÕs need to leave the cave in PlatoÕs Republic, Book VII. The philosopher returns to the cave to facilitate the enlightenment of his fellows, and to put in order the city and its citizens as well as themselves (Republic 539e540b). Similarly, the Israelites must sojourn in the wilderness so that they may eventually constitute a new more perfect city in accordance with the law received in the wilderness.

In order to bring together the cosmological and psychological dimensions of PhiloÕs typology, it is helpful to note that the laws themselves are described as tupoi, images or impressions which the Israelites are told to stamp upon their hearts. Cosmologically speaking, the law of Moses is a copy of the law of nature.[12] To live in accor­dance with the law of Moses is to live in accordance with the cosmic order created by God. Psychologically speaking, to observe Mosaic law is to efface the evil that results from transgression and foolish­ness, and to restamp oneÕs soul with the character of goodness and virtue. Consider PhiloÕs discussion of how ceasing from work on the seventh day enables a soul to live in accordance with the great arche­type:

 

Let us not then neglect this great archetype of the two best lives, the practical and the contemplative, but with that pattern ever before our eyes engrave in our hearts the clear image and stamp of them both, so making mortal nature, as far as may be, like the immortal by saying and doing what we ought. (Decal. 101)

 

According to Philo, Cain exemplifies the ope of wickedness, while Abel exemplifies that of holiness. In a sense, these biblical charac­ters are types. For every detail related about them in the biblical narrativetheir names, their chosen professions, their conceptions of God and their actionsevery single detail contains a moral les­son about the impression of vice or virtue upon the human soul. I suggest that the reason for this is that Cain and Abel exemplify char­acter traits, and their conflict exemplifies the conflict between these traits in every human soul. The conflict between Cain and Abel becomes an allegory of psychic conflict within the soul of every human being. Moreover they are to be understood as two aspects of a single soul.

According to Philo, CainÕs deepest problem is his flawed concep­tion of God, which is reflected in his very name. For Cain believes himself to possess all things. In contrast, AbelÕs Òname means one who refers (all things) to God.Ó (Sacr. 2).

The brothersÕ chosen professions reflect and reinforce their fun­damental differences. Philo emphasizes that CainÕs chosen profession involves him with earthly and inanimate objects. So he does not choose to prepare for a future life and to pay attention to living things. Similarly, Philo points out that Cain is called a tiller of the soil because he refers all things to himself and to his own mind (Sacr. 51). In fact, it is CainÕs lack of understanding that the land is really foreign and belongs only to God that misleads him in the direction of a selfloving character trait and ultimately causes the destruction of his soul. In contrast, Abel chooses to tend living beings. Thus:

 

AbelÕs choice of work as a shepherd is understood as preparatory to rulership and kingship (QG 1.59)

 

The praiseworthiness of shepherding and its connection to leader­ship is developed further in Life of Moses and again in the essay on the Sacrifices of Abel and Cain:

 

With good reason then is Abel who refers all that is best to God called a shepherd. (Sacr. 51)

 

Unlike Cain, Abel is prepared for a future life:

 

So then when God added the good conviction Abel to the soul, he took away the foolish opinion, Cain. So too, when Abraham left this mortal life, Òhe is added to the people of God,Ó (Gen 25:8), in that he inherited incorruption and became equal to the angels, for angels‑‑­those unbodied and blessed soulsare the host and people of God. (Sacr. 5)

 

The birth of Abel only worsens CainÕs negative disposition. For AbelÕs disposition is preferable to CainÕs, and so CainÕs soul abandons him when Abel is born.

 

It is a fact that there are two opposite and contending views of life, one which ascribes all things to the mind as our master, whether we are using our reason or our senses, in motion or at rest, the other which follows God, whose handiwork it believes itself to be ... Now both these views or conceptions lie in the womb of the single soul. But when they are brought to the birth they must be separated, for enemies cannot live together forever. Thus, so long as the soul had not brought forth the Godloving principle in Abel, the selfloving prin­ciple in Cain made her his dwelling. But when she bore the principle which acknowledges the Cause, she abandoned that which looks to the mind with its fancied wisdom. (Sacr. 24)

 

As Philo goes on to say, the two opposite views of life represented by Cain and Abel cannot coexist in peace. Like Jacob and Esau, Cain and Abel must be separated:

 

She had conceived the two contending natures of good and evil and considered earnestly, as wisdom bade her, received a vivid impression of each, when she perceived them leaping and as in a skirmish pre­luding the war that should be between them. And therefore she besought God to show her what had befallen her, and how it might be reme­died. He answered her question thus: Òtwo nations are in the womb.Ó That was what had befallen herto bear both good and evil. But again Òtwo peoples shall be separated from thy womb.Ó This is the remedy, that good and evil be separated and set apart from each other and no longer have the same habitation. (Sacr. 4)

 

Note that, by the time of Jacob and Esau, the philautos (the selflover) has become a type of a whole character and not just a character trait or type. However, according to Philo, Cain and Abel may rep­resent character traits, but not complete characters.

      The types of Cain and Abel do not live in sufficient separation, and they come into conflict as a result of their different conceptions of worship. Reinforcing through his daily actions his misconceived sense of his own importance, CainÕs type is that of selflover: Ôthe philautos (Sacr. 3). Consequently, he is in no hurry to thank God for what he takes to be the fruits of his own labor. And, when he gets around to it, he selfishly fails to offer the first of his crops to God. Instead, he keeps the first and the best for himself. Again, Cain understands the land to be his, while in fact it belongs to God. For Cain, humanity comes first and his sustenance is more important than the acknowledgment of God:

 

There are two charges against the selflover (i.e., Cain): one that he made his thankoffering to God Òafter some daysÓ[13] instead of at once; the other that he offered of the fruits and not of the earliest fruits, or in a single word the first fruits. (Sacr. 52)

 

Those who assert that everything that is involved in thought or per­ception or speech is a free gift of their own soul, seeing that they introduce an impious and atheistic opinion, must be assigned to the race of Cain, who, while incapable even of ruling himself, made bold to say that he had full possession of all other things as well. (Post. 42)

 

These charges are not directed only at Cain. They are directed at every selfloverthat is at anyone who allows the type of Cain to become the dominant character trait in oneÕs soul. AbelÕs sacrifice, however, illustrates further his Godloving nature:

 

But Abel brought other offerings and in other manner. His offering was living, CainÕs was lifeless. His was first in age and value, CainÕs but second. His had strength and superior fatness, CainÕs had but weakness. For we are told that Abel offered of the firstlings of the sheep and of their fat (Gen 4:4). (Sacr. 88)

 

 

Again, of AbelÕs sacrifice Philo writes:

 

Abel offers the firstlings not only from the firstborn, but from the fat, showing that the gladness and richness of the soul, all that protects and gives joy, should be set apart for God. (Sacr. 136)

 

Again, Philo is not writing only about Abel, that is, the character in the Genesis narrative. For Philo, the narrative is about the char­acter trait in the soul. The character trait of virtue is imprinted upon the soul in the form of grateful, joyous acknowledgement of God. Of course, God prefers AbelÕs sacrifice. And it is in jealous response to GodÕs preferential treatment that Cain kills Abel. But this evil act does not solve CainÕs problem. It only exacerbates his problem by removing the possibility that Cain will come under AbelÕs virtuous influence:

 

It would have been to the advantage of Cain, the lover of self, to have guarded Abel; for had he carefully preserved him, he would have been able to lay claim only to a mixed Òhalf and halfÓ life indeed, but would not have drained the cup of sheer unmitigated wickedness. (Det. 68)

 

Thus vice is selfdestructive. Indeed, Philo argues that it is prefer­able to die like Abel than to live like Cain, in a state of eternal death:

 

But in my judgement and in that of my friends, preferable to life with impious men would be death with pious men; for awaiting those who die in this way there will be undying life, but awaiting those who live in that way there will be eternal death. (Post. 39)

 

Immediately after CainÕs fratricide, God asks him, ÒWhere is your brother?Ó According to Philo, the point of GodÕs question is to offer Cain an opportunity to confess his sin and to repent:

 

Why does he who knows all ask the fratricide, ÔWhere is Abel, your brother?Õ He wishes that man himself of his own will shall confess, in order that he may not pretend that all things seem to come about through necessity. For he who killed through necessity would confess that he acted unwillingly; for that which is not in our power is not to be blamed. But he who sins of his own free will denies it, for sinners are obliged to repent. Accordingly he [Moses] inserts in all parts of his legislation that the Deity is not the cause of evil. (QG 1.68)

 

Cain rejects the offer to repent. Still, GodÕs question, as interpreted by Philo, is of great significance. For it shows that repentance is always possible, even for someone whose vicious character is inscribed in his very name. Consequently, although God created everything, including the archetype of evil, only man is responsible for the evil impressed upon his soul and realized in the world.

The murder of Abel certainly does not succeed in exterminating virtue from biblical history. For Seth, who is born after AbelÕs death, continues to exemplify the type of goodness and holiness exemplified by his dead brother.[14] Later, all those who are deemed righteous are considered to be from the Òseed of Seth,Ó while all those who are deemed evil are said to be from the Òseed of Cain.Ó[15]

 

Those who assert that everything that is involved in thought or per­ception or speech is a free gift of their own soul, seeing that they introduce an impious and atheistic opinion, must be assigned to the race of Cain, who, while incapable even of ruling himself, made bold to say that he had full possession of all other things as well. But those who do not claim as their own all that is fair in creation, but acknowl­edge all as due to the gift of God, being men of real nobility, sprung not from a long line of rich ancestors but from lovers of virtue, must remain enrolled under Seth as the head of their race. (Post. 42)

 

This passage brings out two points to which I want to give special emphasis. First, in PhiloÕs view, theology is the root of all good and of all evil. For it is first and foremost oneÕs conception of God, and of oneÕs own relation to the cosmos created by God, that impresses either the type of virtue or the type of vice upon oneÕs soul. It is from oneÕs theology that choices and actions flow, actions that tend to reinforce the initial impression of good or evil. And it is oneÕs theology that determines whether one belongs to the race of Cain or to the race of Sethalthough, as I have said, Philo thinks that repentance is always possible. Second, the story of Cain and Abel is important because they exemplify the ways in which the arche­types of virtue and vicethe tree of life and the tree of knowledge of good and evilmay come to leave their copies upon the human soul. In PhiloÕs view, our situation is fundamentally that of Cain and Abel. We inhabit the same cosmos, and the formation of our souls is no less dependent on our theological convictions, on the choices we make, on the actions we perform, and on the influences to which we expose ourselves. So we have much to learn from Cain and Abel. For they pioneered the kind of life that each of us must live. And their tragic story exemplifies the pitfalls we must all seek to avoid.

Since Cain and Abel exemplify typesat once cosmological and psychologicalit is not surprising that they are echoed by their suc­cessors in the biblical narratives. Thus Philo compares Abraham, Jacob, Isaac and Moses with Abel. And he compares Esau and Laban to Cain. In this way, PhiloÕs typological interpretation of the Cain and Abel story enables him to use that story as a lens through which to read other biblical narratives.

At the same time, however, Philo also reads the Cain and Abel narrative through a lens provided by other biblical passages. In par­ticular, Philo repeatedly connects Cain and Abel with laws that are given only later in the biblical story. This is because, I suggest, Cain and Abel represent the problem for which the law of Moses is the solution. As the story of Cain and Abel shows, we are all highly impressionable and therefore capable of great good or great evil, and each of us is responsible for the effects upon our soul of every choice or action. However, as I said earlier, the laws of Moses are images or impressions, which the Israelites are told to stamp upon their hearts. The laws provide, as it were, solutions to the problems exemplified by Cain. They are designed to implant healthy theo­logical convictions, to efface evil impressions and to reinforce good ones. Thus, for example, the tiller of soil is commanded to bring the first fruits as an offering to God, and to profess GodÕs domin­ion over a land to which the farmer is ultimately foreign. PhiloÕs analysis of Cain brings out the wisdom of this law, which manifests a deep understanding of the human soul.

I have argued, then, that PhiloÕs interpretation of the Cain and Abel narrative in Genesis 4 may justly be called typological, and that his typology has both cosmological and psychological dimen­sions. Indeed, the children of Eve have a special importance within PhiloÕs biblical exegesis as a whole. For their story illustratesin an exemplary fashionsome of the central presuppositions of PhiloÕs exegetical endeavor: the impressionability of the human soul, which can be horrifying or sublime; the responsibility of each individual for himself or herself, which is endless; and the intimate relationship between cosmic structures and Mosaic laws, which both stem from a single creator and from a perfect paradigm.



[1] I have benefited from the incisive comments of John Cavadini, Mary Rose D'Angelo, Paul Franks, Eric Gruen, Graham Hammill, Blake Leyerle, John P. Meier, Judith Newman, David O'Connor, Michael Signer and Gregory E. Sterling.

[2] J. Danielou, From Shadows to Reality: Studies in the Biblical Typology of the Fathers, London 1960 and Jon Whitman, Interpretation and Allegory: Antiquity to the Modern Period, Leiden 2000, esp. 33451 K.J. Woolcombe, ÒThe Biblical Origins and Patrisitic Development of TypologyÓ, in Essays on Typology, Naperville, 1957, 3975.

[3] See Thomas H. Luxon, Literal Figures: Puritan Allegory and the Reformation Crisis in Representation, Chicago, 1995, 3476.

[4] E.g., De Opif. Mundi 19, 34, 71; Leg. 1.61, 1,100, 3.83; Sacr. 135, 137; Det. 76 78, 83; Post. 94, 99; Deus 43‑44; Mos. 2.76; Decal. 101.

[5] L. Goppelt, TYPOS: The Typological Interpretation of the Old Testament in the New, Grand Rapids 1982, TYPOS, 46.

[6] See Luxon, 53: ÒThe real reality signified in typology turns out to be every bit as ahistorical, spiritual, eternal, timeless, ever present (and so, historically speaking, ever absent) as God and his majesty, the very things typology was first defined as prohibited from figuring.Ó

[7] Woolcombe, ÒThe Biblical Origins and Patristic Development of TypologyÓ, 65.

[8] On the deep connections between Jewish and Christian interpretive traditions, see James L. Kugel, Traditions of the Bible: A Guide to the Bible as it was at the start of the Common Era, Cambridge, 1998, and Daniel Boyarin, Border Lines‑ Hybrids, Heretics, and the Partition of Judaeo‑Christianity, Philadelphia 2004.

[9] Goppelt, Typos, 48.

[10] Cf. John Chrysostom, On Vainglory, 39 where the Cain and Abel narrative is taken to be an important text for moral pedagogy. See also L. Kovacs, ÒDivine Pedagogy and the Gnostic Teacher according to Clement of AlexandriaÓ, JECS 9 (2001), 3‑25.

[11] See, e.g., Leg. 1.61 where character is a synonym for tuposis.

[12] See my article ÒA Written Copy of the Law of Nature: an Unthinkable Paradox?Ó StPhA 15 (2003) forthcoming.

[13] Philo is referring to Gen. 4:3.

[14] Although the biblical text implies that Seth is a replacement for Abel, Philo explicitly rejects the idea that one person can replace another.

[15] For further discussion about the descendents of Cain and Seth see the contributions of J. Tubach and G.P. Luttikhuizen to this volume, below, pp. 187201 and 20317.