RATIONALISM, MOTIVATION, AND TIME IN DOSTOEVSKY'S "NOTES FROM THE
UNDERGROUND"
Gary Rosenshield, University of Wisconsin – Madison
Among the most perplexing, but infrequently treated, questions relating to Dostoevsky's "Notes from the Underground" is the origin of the Underground Man's rationalism, a question which, as we shall see, is especially important because of its bearing on the role of métonymie motivation in the novel and on the often baffling relationship between present and past events and narrative planes. The reason this question has received so little attention is that despite Joseph Frank's convincing demonstration of the Underground Man's rationalism in the first chapters of Part One of the novel, the Underground Man is still generally viewed as an out-and-out irrationalist and an implacable foe of rationalism in all its forms. (1) But the Underground Man's rationalism is unmistakable, and as I have attempted to show elsewhere, it appears not only in the first few chapters of Part One but throughout the entire first part. (2) The polemic that the Underground Man engages in with his ideological opponents, "the gentlemen (gospoda), " on the question of the limitations of the rational intellect and man's need for freedom is really an expression of an internal polemic raging within himself, in which he pretends to be playing only one of the two roles, that of the irrationalist. The reason that the Underground Man rages at the gentlemen who advance the deterministic arguments of the Socialists is that he senses that he, too, is still a rationalist and thus cannot free himself of the very beliefs that his irrational self finds so demeaning and simplistic.
In addition to pointing out the Underground Man's rationalism, Frank
also offered an explanation of its origin in nineteenth-century Russian
intellectual history, arguing that the Underground Man is a figure
representing two stages in the development of the Russian
intelligentsia. Whereas in Part Two the Underground Man is presented as
a romantic idealist of the 1840's, a member of a generation which
attempted to escape the sordidness of reality by retreating to an ideal
world "of the good and the beautiful, " Schiller's "das Schöne und
Erhabene" ; in Part One, he emerges as a representative of the next,
the second stage in the development of the Russian intelligentsia, in
which it succumbed to the influence of nihilism: that is the
rationalistic philosophy of Chernyshevskij and his followers. (3) As
Frank says, "Dostoevsky assimilates the major doctrines of Russian
Nihilism in the life of the underground man. . . The first section
shows the underground man in the ideological grip of the Nihilism of
the Sixties; the second, as a perfect product of the social Romanticism
of the Forties. " (4)
88
The main problem with Frank's thesis, it seems to me, is the
interpretation of the Underground Man as a representative of the
nihilism of the 1860's. The ideological transformation that the
Underground Man would have had to undergo to become a nihilist was not
one experienced by many Russian intellectuals of the forties. Indeed,
when this generation of intellectuals in middle age dramatically
altered its political philosophy, it almost invariably discarded its
liberal and radical ideas for conservative or even reactionary ones -
needless to say, a phenomenon not unique to nineteenth-century Russia.
(5) Moreover, even in fiction, the Russian romantics of the forties did
not become the nihilists of the sixties: the Stepan Trofimoviches may
have laid the groundwork for Bazarov, Stavrogin, and Petr Verkhovenskij
- a view which Dostoevsky argues in "The Possessed" - but they did not
themselves become nihilists; and as Turgenev shows in "Fathers and
Sons" the romantic idealists of the forties were generally of a
different class from the radical intelligentsia of the sixties.
Frank does not present the older Underground Man as a perfect
representative of Chernyshevskian ideology; in fact, he argues that the
Underground Man's rebellion against determinism in Part One is evidence
of the continued existence in his personality of the emotions,
morality, and ideology of the romantic idealist of the forties, and it
is this rebellion that constitutes the drama of the novel. But the
Underground Man's rationalism, his even partial acceptance of the
rationalist views of Chernyshevskij, does not seem psychologically and
historically credible given the personality of the Underground Man and
the times in which he lives.
The only way to interpret the Underground Man both as a man of the
forties and a man of the sixties - which Frank ends up doing - is to
conceive of him not primarily as a psychological figure but as an
ideological type, the main function of which is to dramatize the
satiric intentions of the author. If such is the case, there clearly is
no need to motivate metonymically - that is, in terms of psychology and
environment - the Underground Man's change from the ideals of the
forties to the determinism of the sixties. (6) The problem, however, is
that this ideological view of the Underground Man is inconsistent with
Frank's almost exclusive reliance on psychology to interpret the nature
of the Underground Man's revolt against determinism in the first
chapters of Part One. But just as important, by partly reducing the
Underground Man to an ideological type - and a composite one at that -
Frank robs him of the psychological complexity that gives immediacy and
meaning to the very philosophical positions that represent in Frank's
view the heart of the novel.
But if Dostoevsky did not motivate the Underground Man's rationalism
in Russian intellectual history - or did not do it well - it is natural
to assume that he must have grounded this rationalism in the
Underground Man's psychological development, much as he did the
Underground Man's irra-
89
tionalism. The Underground Man's irrationalism, even his insistence
that man ought to act irrationally on purpose to prove himself free,
can be seen to stem logically from an honest attempt to understand his
own irrational behavior, sixteen years earlier, in Part Two. But his
conclusions seem consistent even if one interprets them as
rationalizations of his past reprehensible actions, that is, as an
attempt of a thoroughgoing rationalist to pass himself off as an
irrationalist in order to exonerate himself of responsibility in his
own eyes and the eyes of the reader for the "crime" he committed
against the innocent and defenseless Liza - the implied argument being
that he was bound to act as he did because man is by nature irrational
and thus he cannot help but act against his own interest; (7) or that
he was bound to act against his own interest because only by doing so
could he really prove to himself that he was free, much as Kirillov
believed he was compelled to commit suicide to prove that he was God.
Furthermore, a good case can be made to show that it is not only the
Underground Man's present irrational ideas that are motivated by the
past, but his present irrational behavior as well. After the
frustrating and humiliating experiences of sixteen years earlier, one
expects to find the Underground Man even less rational; for humiliation
and frustration, as we see in Part Two, only exacerbate his irrational
proclivities.
Whereas, however, the link between the Underground Man's past
irrational behavior and his present irrationalist philosophy is
apparent, the rationalist arguments of the forty-year-old narrator, so
evident in his deterministic explanations of his own behavior in the
first half of Part One, seem to be almost completely absent in his
presentation of his younger self in Part Two. For want of any other
evidence one is tempted to see the Underground Man's rationalism as the
end product of his great, even excessive dependence on the intellect in
youth. But there is no evidence in Part Two that the Underground Man's
intellect either at sixteen (the time of his early years at school) or
at twenty-four (the time of his encounters with Zverkov and Liza) was
essentially a rational one or that it was its rational character that
created the Underground Man's numerous problems. This is substantiated
by all the major episodes of Part Two. For example, the incident with
the officer by whom the Underground Man is humiliated - or by whom he
thinks he was humiliated - and on whom he seeks to revenge himself,
would seem to be tailor-made for proving the Underground Man's
rationalist theories of Part One. He had argued there that man cannot
act because he thinks too much; for the more he thinks the more he
realizes that there can be no just reason for exacting revenge (revenge
being the strongest motivation for action that the Underground Man can
think of); that those responsible for insulting you are not to blame,
since, not having free will, they acted as they had to, as the laws of
nature demanded. Classical determinism is used to explain and justify
inertia. And in fact, the Underground Man does not take action against
the officer because he cannot stop thinking and just act. When he
finally collides with the officer on the street, it is by accident, and
only after having in his own mind given up on the project. Many reasons
could be given for the Underground Man's long period of inaction; but
nowhere does the narrator indicate or even imply that his failure to
act promptly
90
resulted from his belief that action was pointless in a world
governed by the laws of nature; he does not even mention the laws of
nature, determinism, or rationalism. To be sure, the Underground Man's
inertia may be ascribed to thinking too much, but not to thinking in
that rationalistic manner which in the early sections of Part One is
shown to lead directly to inertia.
The Underground Man's head is largely responsible for the
misfortunes that occur to him in the two remaining incidents of Part
Two, the Zverkov and Liza episodes. Again, however, it is not the
rational intellect that guides his actions, but his irrational impulses
and drives. Both episodes, like the one with the officer treated above,
are perfect examples of that irrational, self-destructive behavior
discussed in detail by the older Underground Man in the second half of
Part One. It is not that the behavior of twenty-four-year olds in
fiction cannot be ruled by rationalistic thinking; "Crime and
Punishment, " written one year after "Notes from the Underground, "
presents in Raskol'nikov a young man of twenty-four, similar to the
Underground Man in many ways, whose actions are shown to be the direct
result of rationalistic thinking carried to the logical extreme. Of
course, it is not inconceivable that the Underground Man was a
rationalist, too, at twenty-four; however, we are not told or shown it.
Moreover, since the events in Part Two take place sometime in the late
1840's and the Underground Man at that time was somewhat of a romantic
idealist, although already having undergone significant
disillusionment, he must have developed his rationalist side, if we
still want to understand the Underground Man's development against the
historical background, a good deal after: that is, in the early
sixties.
The Jack of psychological motivation of the Underground Man's
rationalism may at first seem an anomaly in Dostoevsky's major fiction,
but it appears much less so when we actually look closely at his
handling of the past in his other novels, and compare it with the
treatment of past events in the novels of his contemporaries.
Russian realists tend to provide psychological motivations for the
behavior of their characters in the fictional present, but they differ
significantly - sometimes being poles apart - in their methods of
linking the action proper of the novel with preceding events. At one
extreme we find Tolstoj, who spends hundreds of pages in "Anna
Karenina" delving into the situation and psychology of Anna and her
husband, but devotes only a few paragraphs to their past lives. At the
other extreme, Turgenev, showing a great affinity to such French
realists as Balzac and Flaubert, often takes pains to explain his
characters' present in terms of their past, devoting, for example, over
one-fifth of his "Nest of Gentlefolk" ("Dvorjanskoe gnezdo") to a
flashback in which he recounts in copious detail, from his own person,
the upbringing and education of his hero, Lavreckij. (His other novels
have similar flashbacks and Vorgeschichten). Dostoevsky's method in his
later novels is somewhere midway between that of Turgenev and Tolstoj.
We get more background than in Tolstoj, and it is for the most part
causally related to the action proper, but it is still
91
relatively brief and does not play a significant role in the novel
in terms of motivation. In "The Idiot, " the prehistory of Prince
Myshkin's stay in Switzerland, from which he leaves with his health
considerably improved, does not lead directly to his physical and
mental collapse once back in Russia; in "The Possessed, " there are a
few pages on the upbringing and the education of Stavrogin under the
tutelage of Stepan Trofimovich Verkhovenskij, but Stepan Trofimovich,
despite his ideological responsibility for the devils, had little
lasting influence on the mature Stavrogin; and in "The Brothers
Karamazov, " there are a few chapters at the beginning sketching the
early years of the brothers, but here the past is not shown to have had
a determining role on the development of character. Ivan and Alesha had
the same parents, and they were brought up in the same environment,
first at home and then at the Polenovs; but from their earliest years
they differed widely in mental outlook and temperament, and of course,
they turn out quite differently. In "Crime and Punishment, " the work
chronologically and thematically nearest to "Notes from the
Underground, " we learn very little of Raskolnikov's past, and the
little we learn of it (for example, in Raskol'nikov's first nightmare
and in his mother's letter in Part One) has to do only with his early
childhood. That the religious, compassionate, ten-year-old Raskol'nikov
who sheds tears over his grandmother's grave could turn into the
rational theorist and murderer of the novel proper is certainly
possible; but, on the other hand, it is by no means probable and the
novel does not attempt to make it seem so. Dostoevsky, for example,
spends no time whatever describing the process of Raskol'nikov's
corruption as Balzac does with Rastignac and Flaubert with Emma Bovary;
Raskol'nikov is already seriously infected with Western rationalistic
ideas the first time we meet him and Dostoevsky takes him from there.
"Notes from the Underground, " however, because of its complex
narrative and temporal structure, differs greatly from Dostoevsky's
other major novels in its integration of past and present. It covers
three distinct and unusually presented periods in the life of its hero:
the first encompassing the Underground Man's years at a boarding school
where he met Zverkov, but focusing on his sixteenth year; the second,
the activities of the Underground Man some eight years later, recounted
in the "officer, " Zverkov, and Liza episodes; and the third, the time
of Part One and the narration of Part Two. The first period constitutes
only several pages of the second part, but it provides a solid
psychological foundation for understanding the twenty-four-year-old
Underground Man's situation eight years later in Petersburg. In fact,
there is curiously a much more direct causal relationship between the
first and second periods than between the second and third. In Part Two
we have a narrator writing in the present showing how several of his
most significant experiences sixteen years earlier (second period) were
directly related to even earlier experiences at school (first period).
We must, of course, be wary of what the Underground Man relates about
his past - he is not the most reliable of narrators - nevertheless,
there is much that he recounts about his childhood that we need not
question. The Underground Man was an orphan unloved by the distant
relatives who brought him up. He was sent away to
92
school where his hypersensitivity, pride, and consciousness of his
social and physical inferiority - he was short, plain, and thin - made
his life as painful as an adolescent as it soon would be as a young
adult. He was somewhat able to overcome his sense of inferiority by
becoming one of the best students at school. But however much he
convinced himself that he was beyond the other boys, he remained as
vulnerable to their opinions as before and even more resentful of what
he thought was their undeserved power over him. His feeling of
powerlessness fostered the desire for domination, and when the occasion
arose in which he could lord it over one of his schoolmates he took
full advantage of it. He recalls in this regard a friendship he had at
school. "Once I did have a friend. But I was already a despot at heart;
I wanted to wield unlimited power over his soul; I sought to instill in
him contempt for his surroundings; I demanded his complete and
disdainful break with these surroundings. I frightened him off with my
passionate friendship; I'd reduce him to tears, to convulsions. He was
a naive and devoted soul; but when he submitted himself to me
completely, I immediately began to detest him and repulsed him - as
though all I needed him for was merely to conquer, to subjugate him. "
(8)
It is not difficult to see that the Underground Man's character at
twenty-four, as presented by the forty-year-old narrator, differs
little from his character at sixteen: he is plagued by the same
problems and resorts to the same counterproductive solutions. The
twenty-four-year-old Underground Man differs only in that he seems to
have taken various of the negative aspects of his personality at
sixteen to their logical conclusions. The incidents with the "officer"
and with Zverkov call to mind the Underground Man's acute sense of
social and physical inferiority and his need to show himself morally -
that is, intellectually and culturally -superior to his adversaries.
His relationship with his one friend at school, which shows his need to
humiliate and subject another human being to his will as compensation
for his own frequent humiliations, exactly parallels his relationship
with Liza, whom the Underground Man humiliates for the humiliation he
experienced at the going-away party for Zverkov. One of the functions
of the portrayal of the sixteen-year-old Underground Man is to show how
he failed to grow and mature, how he remained emotionally at
twenty-four the same person he was at sixteen. But the portrayal is
also predictive: the behavior of the adult is prefigured in the
behavior of the adolescent, and even more important, it is shown
logically, if not necessarily, to arise out of it. What was to happen
to the twenty-four-old Underground Man is presented as not only
possible but even probable.
An unfortunate consequence, perhaps, of presenting a strict
correlation between the past time periods in Part Two is that one
expects a similarly close correlation between periods two and three,
between the relatively more recent past and the present. If the
behavior of the twenty-four-year-old Underground Man arises
consistently from the behavior of his sixteen-year-old counterpart,
should not the rationalism of the forty-year-old hero arise just as
consistently from his twenty-four-year-old counterpart. As we have seen
such a connection between the twenty-four-
93
and forty-year-old Underground Man does not exist; and the fact that
it does not is underlined by the existence of the obviously close
connection between the sixteen- and twenty-four-year-old Underground
Man. One way out of this dilemma, of course, is to argue that the older
Underground Man's rationalism is insincere, that he uses deterministic
reasoning merely to rationalize his reprehensible behavior sixteen
years earlier. Clearly if rationalism has no foundation in the older
Underground Man's personality the whole question of the Underground
Man's early rationalism is simply without point. The argument, however
that the Underground Man's rationalism is only a means of justifying
his past actions - that is, not taking responsibility for them - is
seriously undercut by the Underground Man's passionate belief in free
will and the need to take responsibility, even, as he says, when one is
clearly not responsible according to the laws of nature.
Another argument that might be advanced to account for the absence
of any psychological motivation for the Underground Man's rationalism,
an argument that is perhaps implied in some of the philosophical
interpretations of the novel, is that the "Notes" is not really a novel
at all, but a combination of a philosophical tale and a confession,
genres whose aesthetic laws differ from that of the novel, and thus are
not conducive to being evaluated by criteria - metonymic motivation,
for example - which are inappropriate to it. (9) One would certainly
not use the same approach for Voltaire's "Candide" as one would for
"Crime and Punishment. " But despite the first-person form and the
polemical and philosophical content of Part One, the "Notes" does not
differ from Dostoevsky's later novels in its method of integrating
psychology and action; in fact, its method is almost identical to the
one used in "Crime and Punishment" to present Raskol'nikov. And as we
have seen, with the exception of his rationalism, most of the
Underground Man's actions and ideas seem well motivated in terms of
psychology and environment. The form of the "Notes" is to be sure an
unusual one for a novel, but it is a novel nevertheless, and any
attempt to deal with it as if it were not will probably create more
problems than it will solve.
One might also argue that the novel is constructed so as to
frustrate our attempts to discover the seeds of the Underground Man's
rationalism in his youth; and further, that the novel actively works
against any reconciliation of Parts One and Two in an imaginative
synthesis. According to such a view, the point that the novel makes is
that there exists no necessary relationship between past and present
and any attempt to argue such a relationship is doomed to failure, for
the novel itself is about life's resistance to the imposition on it of
any abstract or logical categories, even that of the self, a personal
entity that maintains its identity through time. (10)
But does the "Notes" really make us reconsider our notions of
causality, or at least, fictional causality? One perhaps could make a
good case for such a view in Gogol's "Dead Souls" in which it seems
that by presenting Chichikov's background near the end of the novel,
Gogol' is in part making
94
fun at the growing Tendency in French literature to employ more
realistic motivation, particularly by means of long introductions
crammed with detailed background information on the characters and
their times. With regard to the "Notes, " however, such a view is
undercut by the psychological links between periods one and two in Part
Two and that between the irrational selves of the Underground Man in
periods one through three. Nevertheless, although it does not seem that
the "Notes" is working to frustrate any attempts to reconcile past and
present, it is still evident that if one is to understand the
Underground Man's rationalism in the present it is perhaps vain, given
the evidence, to insist on deriving it from his past experiences. Once,
however, we have established the absence of any strong psychological
motivation of the Underground Man's rationalism, we can ask in what
other ways might this rationalism be motivated and what harm, if any,
does this absence of psychological motivation do to the novel.
One of the reasons that Dostoevsky did not, it seems to me, motivate
the Underground Man's rationalism of Part One in terms of psychology
and environment is that the large time period between the two parts
made it unnecessary. I have already noted that in his later novels
there is little strict cause and effect relationship between the past
as represented in background information and the action proper of the
present. With regard to the presentation of rationalism, the "Notes"
differs from these novels not in that the causal relationship between
the past and present is significantly weaker, but that the past
constitutes the largest part of the novel and its occurrence after the
present naturally places on it a great deal of emphasis. Yet it seems
that in Dostoevsky's later fiction what is most important in
determining whether the past is to be directly and causally related to
the present is not so much the emphasis that the past receives but the
gap that physically and temporally separates it from the present. In
Part Two, for example, periods one and two are causally related because
period one is used to explain the Underground Man's situation in period
two when the Underground Man was twenty-four years old. Period one is
not separated from period two in the text by any formal means, but is
included in the discussion of period two. We would expect periods one
and two to be directly related because the Underground Man cites his
behavior in period one in order to throw light on his behavior in
period two. Periods two "and three, however, are separated by a formal
division. In addition, there is little or no interpolated material in
Part One (period three) in which period two is used to explain the
Underground Man's behavior in period three.
The temporal and formal gap that we find in the "Notes" and the way
Dostoevsky handles it is not unique in his later work. We find similar
gaps in the epilogues of "The Idiot" and "Crime and Punishment. " In
the second chapter of the epilogue of "Crime and Punishment, " which
takes place nine months after Raskolnikov's trial, a relatively long
period of time considering the entire novel proper occupies only about
two weeks, Raskol'nikov experiences a resurrection from the dead. Since
it is presented as a miracle, it is not treated, and cannot be treated,
in
95
psychological terms, other than by showing in the novel proper that
the ground had been receptive for it. If it had been probable, it would
not, of course, have been a miracle; one cannot have miracles and
psychological probabilities at the same time. Yet there are critics who
have taken Dostoevsky to task for not motivating Raskolnikov's rebirth
in the same slow and detailed psychological manner that he motivated
Raskolnikov's murder and his consequent suffering. (11) Although
Dostoevsky did not and could not use the same motivation for the murder
and the miracle, he does not at all imply that nothing important was
going on in Raskolnikov's psyche all those months spent in prison
before his spiritual awakening. It was simply unnecessary to show the
process of the rebirth - even if it could be showed - as long as it was
still a possibility. The same approach seems to hold for the motivation
of the Underground Man's rationalism in Part One. It does not seem at
all probable that the Underground Man's reliance on and high regard for
his intellect would have had to develop into the rationalism of Part
One, but the possibility - at least psychologically, if not
historically - certainly cannot be denied; and it is not a question
here of the smallest mathematical possibility, but possibility well
grounded in fictional verisimilitude. The novel asks us to accept that
sometime during the sixteen year gap between Parts One and Two the
Underground Man's intellectual development took a course that led to
the rationalism of the first chapters of Part One.
Furthermore, the reversed chronology of the two parts, somewhat
surprisingly, does not really increase the emphasis on causation. In
fact, it seems more likely that the two parts are in reverse
chronological order primarily for the sake of presenting the
Underground Man's formal argument against determinism - the
generalizations of the shorter Part One preceding, as we might expect,
the detailed proof of Part Two. The gap, however, between Parts One and
Two, so unconducive to establishing necessary causal relations between
the younger and older hero, is not at all detrimental to the
Underground Man's attempt to prove man's irrationality, for which
events from any time would be equally relevant. The thesis and
demonstration form of the "Notes" also partially explains why there is
no mention in Part Two of the Underground Man's rationalistic views:
the Underground Man chooses to write Part Two as proof of only the
irrationalistic propositions of the second half of Part One; therefore
he understandably focuses only on those events in his own experience
that demonstrate man's irrationality. One would hardly expect him,
given his point of view, to dwell on factors which might be interpreted
as strictly determining his development.
But the origins of the Underground Man's rationalism are of
comparatively little significance in the "Notes" most of all because
the focus of the work, despite the detailed recounting of the past, is
not on the past and causation (in the sense of the psychological and
environmental determinants of his behavior), but on the present and on
the dynamics of becoming. The point of view of most of Part Two is
primarily not the consciousness of the younger Underground Man, but
that of the older hero, who is telling the story of his past from the
perspective of a more
96
experienced and relatively wiser man, or at least one who is able to
marvel at his past ignorance and cruelty. He repeatedly alludes, for
example, to his failure to understand Liza:
I did not even understand that she was deliberately hiding behind a
mask of mockery, that this is usually the last subterfuge of people who are
modest and chaste of heart in the face of rude, importunate attempts to probe
their soul, and who refuse to yield to the very end out of pride and fear of
showing their true feelings. I should have guessed it from the very timidity
with which she tried, repeatedly, to utter her mocking words, until she
finally ventured to speak them. But I did not guess, and a vindictive anger
flared up in me. (p. 115)
I know, I will be told that this is incredible - that it's impossible to be
as cruel and stupid as I was; people may even add that it would be impossible
not to love her, or at least appreciate her love. . . Besides, what is so
incredible about it, when I had already managed to reach such a state of moral
corruption, to lose all touch with "living life" so completely, that only a
little earlier I could reproach and shame her with the accusation that she had
come to me to listen to "pathetic words. " And it didn't even occur to me that
she had come, not at all to listen to pathetic words, but to love me, for in
love a woman finds all resurrection, all salvation from any kind of ruin, all
renewal; indeed, it cannot manifest itself in any other way but this. (pp.
147-148)
Except for the sections of dialogue, most of the descriptions and
analyses of Part Two are presented from the point of view of the older
Underground Man. Expressions like "I did not know then, " "I did not
understand, " "I could not see, " and so forth are common. There is
good reason for this: the Underground Man is not telling about the past
only to prove something to himself about his earlier years or about the
nature of man -he knows these things only too well - he is writing
primarily for himself and for himself now. He is interested in the
past, over which he experiences so much guilt and remorse, because he
sees, or at least senses, that by understanding it and coming to terms
with it he can achieve relief from his spiritual torment and perhaps
even find a way out of his seemingly desperate situation. "Even now, so
many years after, the memory of all this is somehow too distressing.
Many memories distress me now, but. . . shouldn't I perhaps conclude my
'Notes' at this point? It seems to me that it was a mistake to start
them. At any rate, I have felt ashamed throughout the writing of this
story: hence this is no longer literature, but corrective punishment
(ispravitel'noe n a k a z a n i e ). " (p. 151) For Dostoevsky's great
intellectual heroes, in particular Raskol'nikov and Ivan Karamazov,
corrective self-punishment is indeed one of the essential steps on the
road to spiritual recovery. Nor is it chance that the turning point for
both Raskol'nikov and Ivan Karamazov is the confession each makes
toward the end of his respective novel, a sort of self-inflicted
corrective punishment, and one that greatly resembles the "private"
confession that the Underground Man makes in the writing of his notes.
97
The Underground Man, then, reviews the past much less to establish
the inevitability of his present situation, than to assess its
significance for the present. Far from being a determinant of his
present behavior, the past provides the Underground Man with the means
by which he can overcome the present and begin for the first time to
look to the future. The "Notes" is unlike many confessions in which the
sinner, having found his way, can describe the past as past, a stage in
his development that is no longer relevant for this future. The
Underground Man is a sinner who has not yet found the way; and so for
him the past is still a vital and haunting present, the significance of
which must be unravelled so he may overcome his present intolerable
situation.
The Underground Man's implied insistence in Part One that man must
take responsibility for his actions, despite all rational proof that
man is not and cannot be responsible for them, is really an argument
against using the past as an excuse for present behavior. Furthermore,
since the Underground Man at forty, though more perceptive now than
sixteen years before, is essentially the same person with the same
problems as he was at twenty-four, his analysis of the past is
tantamount to an analysis of his personality and situation in the
present. The causal relationship between Parts One and Two is, as it
were, erased as the past and present become one and the interest of the
Underground Man as well as of the reader in Part Two becomes the
Underground Man in the present. It is not that the novel denies the
existence or importance of causes, but that it does not present them as
determinants of behavior. How the Underground Man got into his present
morass becomes less important than how he can make the guilt,
suffering, and knowledge resulting from his past experiences serve as
the basis for spiritual renewal.
The origins of the Underground Man's rationalism must be considered
to be relatively unimportant in the "Notes" ; but the search for these
origins reveals a great deal about the focus and the point of view of
the novel. It reveals that the causes of the Underground Man's
irrationalism, though more consistently motivated in terms of
psychology and environment are no more important ultimately than the
causes of his rationalism, for if the "Notes" is at all a novel about
the past, it is not about its determining effect on the Underground
Man's present, but about the solution to his problems that has lain
buried in it. The Underground Man, the novel implies, can be saved only
when he fully appreciates and accepts the significance of Liza's love
and compassion, when he fully understands that salvation and the
highest affirmation of the self are to be found in the free surrender
of the self to others. (12) The Underground Man, of course, has not yet
come to such an understanding, but as the confession shows, he is much
closer to it than before he began his confession, before he began
actively to seek a solution to the riddle of his unhappy state. (13)
NOTES
98
|